Nature Legal

Abū Rayhān al-Bīrūnī, a medieval scholar, scientist and polymath, understood « natural law » as the survival of the fittest. He argued that the antagonism between people could only be overcome by a divine law, which he believed was sent by prophets. This should also be the general position of the Ashari school, the largest school of Sunni theology,[56] as well as of Ibn Hazm. Thus conceptualized, all « laws » are seen as stemming from subjective attitudes motivated by cultural ideas and individual preferences, and thus the notion of « divine revelation » is justified as a kind of « divine intervention » that replaces human positive laws criticized as relative with a single divine positive law. However, this also means that everything can be included in « divine law » as would be the case in « human laws, » but unlike the latter, « God`s law » is considered binding by virtue of « the power of God, » regardless of the nature of the commandments: since God is not subject to human laws and conventions, He can command anything He wants. Just as he can do what he wants. Escobar`s hippos are far from unique (at least in terms of their claim to personality). Building on his own 2010 article, « Legal Personhood and the Nonhuman Rights Project » (Animal Law 17/1), philosopher and animal rights activist Steven Wise led an animal liberty movement that successfully used the habeas corpus mandate to obtain it—a scripture that generally presupposes that the entity whose freedom is sought is a « person. » Following Wise`s strategy, a group of philosophers wrote a letter in 2018 in support of two captive chimpanzees, Tommy and Kiko, saying they « meet the [personality] criteria and are entitled to habeas corpus. » In 2004, before the Nonhuman Rights Project began, a landmark case called The Cetacean Community vs. George W. Bush asked a U.S. court to decide whether marine mammals had the legal authority to sue on their own behalf. Again, the presumption is that such a legal status derives from personality, although this did not have to be done explicitly until recent years, since the type of people brought to justice was always what we consider paradigmatic: people. But today, at least some rivers are also being reclassified as people.

To harm such a flow is to harm a person, a being who should be considered an end in itself with inalienable rights and intrinsic value. In other words, some legal systems now treat rivers as subject entities that are almost universally recognized as completely devoid of subjective existence. The doctrine holds that nature and its components are not « things » or goods, but living beings with intrinsic value and an inherent right to exist. The idea is centuries old and exists mainly in indigenous and other land-based cultures. But with pollution and deforestation threatening much of the planet, and climate change exacerbating sea-level rise, extreme weather and mass migration, the concept of granting rights to nature has gained prominence and urgency around the world over the past 15 years. Dear Tiffany, thank you very much for bringing this update and the reflections on this topic, which I believe are really helpful in uplifting Stingy and finally drawing attention to the positive actions needed to achieve harmony with nature. Fortescue emphasized « the supreme importance of the law of God and nature » in works that « profoundly influenced the course of legal development in the centuries that followed. » [68] The jurist Ellis Sandoz noted that « the historically ancient law and the ontologically superior law—eternal, divine, natural—are woven into a single harmonious texture in Fortescue`s account of English law. » [69] As legal historian Norman Doe explains, « Fortescue follows the general pattern of Thomas Aquinas. The purpose of every legislator is to incite people to virtue. This is done by law.

Fortescue`s definition of the law (also found in Accursius and Bracton) was, after all, « a sacred sanction that commands what is virtuous [honesta] and forbids the contrary. » [70] Fortescue quoted the great Italian Leonardo Bruni for his statement that « virtue alone begets happiness. » [71] For O`Neal, there is not only his belief that rivers, mountains, and forests have rights, but also a deep belief that those fundamental rights were mistakenly omitted from the U.S. Constitution more than 200 years ago because he calls it a myth about the abundance of nature. With a population of nearly 8 billion, he said, the world is much smaller than we thought. Jurisprudence in natural law is currently in a phase of reformulation (as is legal positivism). The most prominent contemporary naturalist lawyer, Australian John Finnis, is based in Oxford, but there are also Americans Germain Grisez, Robert P. George and Canadian Joseph Boyle and Brazilian Emídio Brasileiro. All have tried to construct a new version of natural law. The 19th century anarchist and legal theorist, Lysander Spooner, was also a figure in the expression of modern natural law. The idea: Nature and ecosystems should no longer be seen as property, but as entities that have a legal and inalienable right to exist, thrive and defend themselves in court as « rights-bearing entities. » Heinrich A.

Rommen notes « the tenacity with which the spirit of English common law maintained the notions of natural law and justice which it had assimilated to the Catholic Middle Ages, thanks in particular to the influence of Henry de Bracton (d. 1268) and Sir John Fortescue († c. 1476). [61] The Bracton translator notes that Bracton was « a jurist by training who had a firm eye on the principles and distinctions of Roman jurisprudence »; but Bracton adapted these principles to English ends, rather than slavishly copying. [62] In particular, Bracton reversed the Roman imperial maxim « The will of the prince is law » and insisted that the king is under the law. [63] Legal historian Charles F. Mullett noted Bracton`s « ethical definition of law, his recognition of justice, and ultimately his devotion to natural rights. » [64] Bracton regarded justice as the « source » from which « all rights flow. » [65] For his definition of justice, Bracton quoted the twelfth-century Italian jurist Azo: « Justice is the constant and infallible will to give everyone his right. » [66] Bracton is the second legal treatise studied by the young apprentice lawyer Thomas Jefferson. [67] « We have to find a balance between nature and trade, and right now we are so out of balance that the world is spiraling out of control, » he said. « We can create a new system, build a body of laws that recognize the fundamental rights of nature. I think this is our last and best hope for saving the planet. « There`s another legal dilemma, » Anozie said. Would natural rights control trees, food sources or water on private lands? Immediately thereafter, a farm organization filed a lawsuit in Federal Court to prevent the legislation from coming into force.

A judge struck it down because it was unconstitutionally vague. Other U.S. conservation laws have been repealed on the grounds that they will be replaced by state laws. However, a growing number of lawsuits involving the rights of nature could set a precedent for national and local governments to advocate for biodiversity conservation by denouncing extractive projects that could prove destructive to a particular ecosystem. The lawsuits also draw attention to environmental justice issues faced by marginalized communities, particularly indigenous communities who are custodians of these vital natural ecosystems and whose livelihoods and cultural and spiritual practices depend on them. Already in the thirteenth century it was said that « the natural law .. is the basis of all laws »[91] and of the clerk and judges that « natural law requires that every man be present before he can be punished; and if he is absent by reservation, he must be summoned to appear and in default. [92] [93] Moreover, we note in 1824 that « the proceedings before our courts are based on the law of England, and that law is again founded on the law of nature and the revealed law of God. If the right of enforcement is incompatible with either of these two, the English courts of first instance cannot recognise it. [94] In the 17th century, the medieval teleological vision was strongly criticized by some circles.

Instead, Thomas Hobbes established a contractual theory of legal positivism about what everyone could agree on: what they sought (happiness) was controversial, but a broad consensus could form around what they feared (violent death at the hands of another).

D'autres actualités...